0

Reading Comprehension

Description: practice questions on reading comprehension
Number of Questions: 23
Created by:
Tags: reading comprehension Reading Comprehension
Attempted 0/23 Correct 0 Score 0

Which of the following cannot be inferred from the passage?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

The idea of materialism in sociology was in itself a stroke of genius. Naturally, for the time being it was only a hypothesis, but one which first created the possibility of a strictly scientific approach to historical and social problems. Hitherto, not knowing how to get down to the simplest primary relations such as those of production, the sociologists undertook the direct investigation and study of political and legal forms, stumbled on the fact that these forms emerge from certain of mankind’s ideas in the period in question—and there they stopped; it appeared as if social relations are consciously established by men. But this conclusion was on complete contradiction to all historical observations. It never has been the case, nor is it so now, that the members of society conceive the sum total of the social relations in which they live as something definite, integral, pervaded by some principle; on the contrary, the mass of people adapt themselves to these relations unconsciously, and have so little conception of them as specific historical social relations that, for instance, an explanation of the exchange relations under which people have lived for centuries was found only in very recent times. Materialism removed this contradiction by carrying the analysis deeper, to the origin of man’s social ideas themselves; and its conclusion that the course of ideas depends on the course of things is the only one compatible with scientific psychology. Further, and from yet another aspect, this hypothesis was the first to elevate sociology to the level of a science. Hitherto, sociologists had found it difficult to distinguish the important and the unimportant in the complex network of social phenomena (that is the root of subjectivism in sociology) and had been unable to discover any objective criterion for such a demarcation. Materialism provided an absolutely objective criterion by singling out ‘production relations’ as the structure of society, and by making it possible to apply these relations that general scientific criterion of recurrence whose applicability to sociology the subjectivists denied. So long as they confined themselves to ideological social relations (i.e., such as, before taking shape, pass through man’s consciousness) they could not observe recurrence and regularity in the social phenomena of the various countries, and their science was at best only a description of these phenomena, a collection of raw material. The analysis of material social relations at once made it possible to observe recurrence and regularity and to generalize the systems of the various countries in the single fundamental concept: social formation. It was this generalization alone that made it possible to proceed from the description of social phenomena (and their evaluation from the standpoint of an ideal) to their strictly scientific analysis, which isolates, let us say by way of example, that which distinguishes one capitalist country from another and investigates that which is common to all of them.

  1. The idea of materialism in sociology was at first only a hypothesis.

  2. What the sociologists discovered subsequently was merely stumbled upon.

  3. The approach of the sociologists was scientific right from the beginning.

  4. What was initially only a hypothesis subsequently led to scientific exploration.

  5. Materialism carried forward the analysis to the origin of man’s social ideas.


Correct Option: C
Explanation:

This does not follow from the passage nor is such an inference a possibility. This is the correct answer.

What, according to the author, is the belief contradicted by the idea of materialism?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

The idea of materialism in sociology was in itself a stroke of genius. Naturally, for the time being it was only a hypothesis, but one which first created the possibility of a strictly scientific approach to historical and social problems. Hitherto, not knowing how to get down to the simplest primary relations such as those of production, the sociologists undertook the direct investigation and study of political and legal forms, stumbled on the fact that these forms emerge from certain of mankind’s ideas in the period in question—and there they stopped; it appeared as if social relations are consciously established by men. But this conclusion was on complete contradiction to all historical observations. It never has been the case, nor is it so now, that the members of society conceive the sum total of the social relations in which they live as something definite, integral, pervaded by some principle; on the contrary, the mass of people adapt themselves to these relations unconsciously, and have so little conception of them as specific historical social relations that, for instance, an explanation of the exchange relations under which people have lived for centuries was found only in very recent times. Materialism removed this contradiction by carrying the analysis deeper, to the origin of man’s social ideas themselves; and its conclusion that the course of ideas depends on the course of things is the only one compatible with scientific psychology. Further, and from yet another aspect, this hypothesis was the first to elevate sociology to the level of a science. Hitherto, sociologists had found it difficult to distinguish the important and the unimportant in the complex network of social phenomena (that is the root of subjectivism in sociology) and had been unable to discover any objective criterion for such a demarcation. Materialism provided an absolutely objective criterion by singling out ‘production relations’ as the structure of society, and by making it possible to apply these relations that general scientific criterion of recurrence whose applicability to sociology the subjectivists denied. So long as they confined themselves to ideological social relations (i.e., such as, before taking shape, pass through man’s consciousness) they could not observe recurrence and regularity in the social phenomena of the various countries, and their science was at best only a description of these phenomena, a collection of raw material. The analysis of material social relations at once made it possible to observe recurrence and regularity and to generalize the systems of the various countries in the single fundamental concept: social formation. It was this generalization alone that made it possible to proceed from the description of social phenomena (and their evaluation from the standpoint of an ideal) to their strictly scientific analysis, which isolates, let us say by way of example, that which distinguishes one capitalist country from another and investigates that which is common to all of them.

  1. Social relations are consciously established by men.

  2. Materialism in sociology was a stroke of genius.

  3. Sum total of the social relations is definite, integral and principled.

  4. Sociology could be elevated to the level of a science.

  5. Exchange relations are a matter of recent discovery.


Correct Option: A
Explanation:

It was this assertion that the author lays bare when he says that this conclusion was in complete contradiction to all historical observations. This answers the question.

Which of the following best describes the approach of the writer?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

The idea of materialism in sociology was in itself a stroke of genius. Naturally, for the time being it was only a hypothesis, but one which first created the possibility of a strictly scientific approach to historical and social problems. Hitherto, not knowing how to get down to the simplest primary relations such as those of production, the sociologists undertook the direct investigation and study of political and legal forms, stumbled on the fact that these forms emerge from certain of mankind’s ideas in the period in question—and there they stopped; it appeared as if social relations are consciously established by men. But this conclusion was on complete contradiction to all historical observations. It never has been the case, nor is it so now, that the members of society conceive the sum total of the social relations in which they live as something definite, integral, pervaded by some principle; on the contrary, the mass of people adapt themselves to these relations unconsciously, and have so little conception of them as specific historical social relations that, for instance, an explanation of the exchange relations under which people have lived for centuries was found only in very recent times. Materialism removed this contradiction by carrying the analysis deeper, to the origin of man’s social ideas themselves; and its conclusion that the course of ideas depends on the course of things is the only one compatible with scientific psychology. Further, and from yet another aspect, this hypothesis was the first to elevate sociology to the level of a science. Hitherto, sociologists had found it difficult to distinguish the important and the unimportant in the complex network of social phenomena (that is the root of subjectivism in sociology) and had been unable to discover any objective criterion for such a demarcation. Materialism provided an absolutely objective criterion by singling out ‘production relations’ as the structure of society, and by making it possible to apply these relations that general scientific criterion of recurrence whose applicability to sociology the subjectivists denied. So long as they confined themselves to ideological social relations (i.e., such as, before taking shape, pass through man’s consciousness) they could not observe recurrence and regularity in the social phenomena of the various countries, and their science was at best only a description of these phenomena, a collection of raw material. The analysis of material social relations at once made it possible to observe recurrence and regularity and to generalize the systems of the various countries in the single fundamental concept: social formation. It was this generalization alone that made it possible to proceed from the description of social phenomena (and their evaluation from the standpoint of an ideal) to their strictly scientific analysis, which isolates, let us say by way of example, that which distinguishes one capitalist country from another and investigates that which is common to all of them.

  1. The writer is far too opinionated in his approach to a serious issue.

  2. The writer bases his conclusions on certain hypotheses and assumptions.

  3. The conclusions of the writer are not based on empirically proven materials.

  4. The writer is hugely assertive about his facts without being sure about them.

  5. The writer makes a scholarly dissertation on an issue that preoccupied him.


Correct Option: C
Explanation:

Such conclusions should generally be based on empirically proven materials that carry conviction. As the writer has not done that, it fails to pass the muster. This is the best description of his approach and a plausible answer to the question.

According to the passage, what is the most important observation of the writer?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

The idea of materialism in sociology was in itself a stroke of genius. Naturally, for the time being it was only a hypothesis, but one which first created the possibility of a strictly scientific approach to historical and social problems. Hitherto, not knowing how to get down to the simplest primary relations such as those of production, the sociologists undertook the direct investigation and study of political and legal forms, stumbled on the fact that these forms emerge from certain of mankind’s ideas in the period in question—and there they stopped; it appeared as if social relations are consciously established by men. But this conclusion was on complete contradiction to all historical observations. It never has been the case, nor is it so now, that the members of society conceive the sum total of the social relations in which they live as something definite, integral, pervaded by some principle; on the contrary, the mass of people adapt themselves to these relations unconsciously, and have so little conception of them as specific historical social relations that, for instance, an explanation of the exchange relations under which people have lived for centuries was found only in very recent times. Materialism removed this contradiction by carrying the analysis deeper, to the origin of man’s social ideas themselves; and its conclusion that the course of ideas depends on the course of things is the only one compatible with scientific psychology. Further, and from yet another aspect, this hypothesis was the first to elevate sociology to the level of a science. Hitherto, sociologists had found it difficult to distinguish the important and the unimportant in the complex network of social phenomena (that is the root of subjectivism in sociology) and had been unable to discover any objective criterion for such a demarcation. Materialism provided an absolutely objective criterion by singling out ‘production relations’ as the structure of society, and by making it possible to apply these relations that general scientific criterion of recurrence whose applicability to sociology the subjectivists denied. So long as they confined themselves to ideological social relations (i.e., such as, before taking shape, pass through man’s consciousness) they could not observe recurrence and regularity in the social phenomena of the various countries, and their science was at best only a description of these phenomena, a collection of raw material. The analysis of material social relations at once made it possible to observe recurrence and regularity and to generalize the systems of the various countries in the single fundamental concept: social formation. It was this generalization alone that made it possible to proceed from the description of social phenomena (and their evaluation from the standpoint of an ideal) to their strictly scientific analysis, which isolates, let us say by way of example, that which distinguishes one capitalist country from another and investigates that which is common to all of them.

  1. Scientific approach to historical and social problems

  2. People adapting to social relations without any design

  3. Conscious effort for establishment of social relations

  4. Elevating the hypothesis of sociology to a level of science

  5. Singling out of ‘production relations’ as the structure of society


Correct Option: B
Explanation:

This is precisely what the writer suggests and emphasises on. This is the correct answer.

The author calls it ‘the root of subjectivism in sociology’. The allusion is to

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

The idea of materialism in sociology was in itself a stroke of genius. Naturally, for the time being it was only a hypothesis, but one which first created the possibility of a strictly scientific approach to historical and social problems. Hitherto, not knowing how to get down to the simplest primary relations such as those of production, the sociologists undertook the direct investigation and study of political and legal forms, stumbled on the fact that these forms emerge from certain of mankind’s ideas in the period in question—and there they stopped; it appeared as if social relations are consciously established by men. But this conclusion was on complete contradiction to all historical observations. It never has been the case, nor is it so now, that the members of society conceive the sum total of the social relations in which they live as something definite, integral, pervaded by some principle; on the contrary, the mass of people adapt themselves to these relations unconsciously, and have so little conception of them as specific historical social relations that, for instance, an explanation of the exchange relations under which people have lived for centuries was found only in very recent times. Materialism removed this contradiction by carrying the analysis deeper, to the origin of man’s social ideas themselves; and its conclusion that the course of ideas depends on the course of things is the only one compatible with scientific psychology. Further, and from yet another aspect, this hypothesis was the first to elevate sociology to the level of a science. Hitherto, sociologists had found it difficult to distinguish the important and the unimportant in the complex network of social phenomena (that is the root of subjectivism in sociology) and had been unable to discover any objective criterion for such a demarcation. Materialism provided an absolutely objective criterion by singling out ‘production relations’ as the structure of society, and by making it possible to apply these relations that general scientific criterion of recurrence whose applicability to sociology the subjectivists denied. So long as they confined themselves to ideological social relations (i.e., such as, before taking shape, pass through man’s consciousness) they could not observe recurrence and regularity in the social phenomena of the various countries, and their science was at best only a description of these phenomena, a collection of raw material. The analysis of material social relations at once made it possible to observe recurrence and regularity and to generalize the systems of the various countries in the single fundamental concept: social formation. It was this generalization alone that made it possible to proceed from the description of social phenomena (and their evaluation from the standpoint of an ideal) to their strictly scientific analysis, which isolates, let us say by way of example, that which distinguishes one capitalist country from another and investigates that which is common to all of them.

  1. lack of objectivity in firming up of social relations

  2. overdependence on hypothesis rather than on science

  3. production relations leading to the structure of society

  4. failure to demarcate the complex network of social phenomena

  5. general scientific criterion of recurrence to sociology denied by the subjectivists


Correct Option: D
Explanation:

It is this complex network of social phenomena that is alluded to while calling it the root of subjectivism in sociology. This is the answer.

According to the passage, ‘fall of the favourite’ is a

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

Although it is generally best not to mix work with friendship, there are times when a friend can be used to greater effect than an enemy. A man of power, for example, often has dirty work that has to be done, but for the sake of appearances it is generally preferable to have other people do it for him; friends often do this the best, since their affection for him makes them willing to take chances. Also, if plans go awry for some reason, the friend can be used as a convenient scapegoat. This ‘fall of the favourite’ was a trick often used by kings and sovereigns. They would let their closest friend at court take the fall for a mistake, since the public would not believe that they would deliberately sacrifice a friend for such purpose. Of course, once the card is played out, the friend is lost forever. It is best, then, to reserve the scapegoat role for someone who is close but not too close.
Finally, the problem about working with friends is that it confuses the boundaries and distances that working requires. But if both partners in the arrangement understand the dangers involved, a friend often can be employed to great effect. One must never let one’s guard down in such a venture, however; always be on the lookout for any signs of emotional disturbance such as envy and ingratitude. Nothing is stable in the realm of power, and even the closest of friends can be transformed into the worst of enemies.
When a friend is hired, his qualities kept hidden for long and let it come to fore by and by. Strangely enough, it is the act of kindness that unbalances everything. People want to feel they deserve their good fortune. The receipt of a favour can become oppressive. He may get a feeling that he has been chosen because he is a friend and not because he merited it. There is almost a touch of condescension in the act of hiring friends that secretly afflicts them. The injury will come out slowly. A little more honesty, flashes of resent and envy here and there, and before it is realized the friendship has faded away. The more favours and gifts one bestows to revive friendship, the less gratitude is received.
Ingratitude has a long and deep history. It has demonstrated its powers for so many centuries, that it is truly amazing that people continue to underestimate them. Better to be wary. One should never expect gratitude from a friend. It will be a pleasant surprise to find that they are actually grateful. The problem with using or hiring friends is that it will inevitably limit the power one intended to have. The friend is rarely the one who is most able to help; and in the end, skill and competence are far more important than friendly feelings.
All working situations require a kind of distance between people. People try to work, not to make friends; friendliness (real or false) only obscures that fact. The key to power is the ability to judge who is best suited to further the interests of an organization in all situations. Keep friends for friendship, but work with the skilled and competent. (Robert Greene in Power)

  1. trick often used by kings and sovereigns

  2. ploy employed at high places for power

  3. act of kindness bestowed on friends

  4. necessary tool in the hands of kings

  5. method to win over friends and foes


Correct Option: A
Explanation:

It was a trick often used by kings and sovereigns for which friends had to be sacrificed. This answers it.

What, according to the author, do people continue to underestimate?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

Although it is generally best not to mix work with friendship, there are times when a friend can be used to greater effect than an enemy. A man of power, for example, often has dirty work that has to be done, but for the sake of appearances it is generally preferable to have other people do it for him; friends often do this the best, since their affection for him makes them willing to take chances. Also, if plans go awry for some reason, the friend can be used as a convenient scapegoat. This ‘fall of the favourite’ was a trick often used by kings and sovereigns. They would let their closest friend at court take the fall for a mistake, since the public would not believe that they would deliberately sacrifice a friend for such purpose. Of course, once the card is played out, the friend is lost forever. It is best, then, to reserve the scapegoat role for someone who is close but not too close.
Finally, the problem about working with friends is that it confuses the boundaries and distances that working requires. But if both partners in the arrangement understand the dangers involved, a friend often can be employed to great effect. One must never let one’s guard down in such a venture, however; always be on the lookout for any signs of emotional disturbance such as envy and ingratitude. Nothing is stable in the realm of power, and even the closest of friends can be transformed into the worst of enemies.
When a friend is hired, his qualities kept hidden for long and let it come to fore by and by. Strangely enough, it is the act of kindness that unbalances everything. People want to feel they deserve their good fortune. The receipt of a favour can become oppressive. He may get a feeling that he has been chosen because he is a friend and not because he merited it. There is almost a touch of condescension in the act of hiring friends that secretly afflicts them. The injury will come out slowly. A little more honesty, flashes of resent and envy here and there, and before it is realized the friendship has faded away. The more favours and gifts one bestows to revive friendship, the less gratitude is received.
Ingratitude has a long and deep history. It has demonstrated its powers for so many centuries, that it is truly amazing that people continue to underestimate them. Better to be wary. One should never expect gratitude from a friend. It will be a pleasant surprise to find that they are actually grateful. The problem with using or hiring friends is that it will inevitably limit the power one intended to have. The friend is rarely the one who is most able to help; and in the end, skill and competence are far more important than friendly feelings.
All working situations require a kind of distance between people. People try to work, not to make friends; friendliness (real or false) only obscures that fact. The key to power is the ability to judge who is best suited to further the interests of an organization in all situations. Keep friends for friendship, but work with the skilled and competent. (Robert Greene in Power)

  1. Uses of friendship

  2. Power of ingratitude

  3. Act of kindness

  4. Touch of condescension

  5. Role of scapegoats


Correct Option: B
Explanation:

Ingratitude has a deep history which, according to the passage, people continue to underestimate. This answers the question.

The writer in the opening sentence says ‘it dreams of social peace’. Here, 'it' refers to

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows:

The bourgeois intelligentsia of the West, like the English Fabians, elevates municipal socialism to a special ‘trend’ precisely because it dreams of social peace, of class conciliation, and seeks to divert public attention away from the fundamental questions of the economic system as a whole, and of the state structure as a whole, to minor questions of local self-government. In the sphere of questions in the first category, the class antagonisms stand out most sharply; that is the sphere which affects the very foundations of the class rule of the bourgeoisie. Hence it is in that sphere that the philistine, reactionary utopia of bringing about socialism piecemeal is particularly hopeless. Attention is diverted to the sphere of minor local questions, being directed not to the question of the class rule of the bourgeoisie, nor to the question of the chief instruments of that rule, but to the question of distributing the crumbs thrown by the rich bourgeoisie for the ‘needs of the population.’ Naturally, since attention is focussed on such questions as the spending of paltry sums (in comparison with the total surplus value and total state expenditure of the bourgeoisie), which the bourgeoisie itself is willing to set aside for public health, or for education (the bourgeoisie must have trained workers able to adapt themselves to a high technical level!), and so on, it is possible, in the sphere of such minor questions, to hold forth about ‘social peace’, about the harmfulness of the class struggle, and so on. What class struggle can there be if the bourgeoisie itself is spending money on the ‘needs of the population’, on public health, on education? What needs is there for a social if it is possible through the local self-governing bodies, gradually, step by step, to extend ‘collective ownership’, and ‘socialistic’ production: the horse tramways, the slaughter-houses etc?
The philistine opportunism of that ‘trend’ lies in the fact that people forget the narrow limits of the so-called ‘municipal socialism’ (in reality, municipal capitalism, as the English Social-Democrats properly point out in their controversies with the Fabians). They forget that so long as the bourgeoisie rules as a class it cannot allow any encroachment, even from the ‘municipal’ point of view, upon the real foundations of its rule; that if the bourgeoisie allows, tolerates, ‘municipal socialism’, it is because the latter does not touch the foundations of its rule, does not interfere with the important sources of its wealth, but extends only to the narrow sphere of local expenditure, which the bourgeoisie itself allows the ‘population’ to manage. It does not need more than a slight acquaintance with ‘municipal socialism’ in the West to know that any attempt on the part of socialist municipalities to go a little beyond the boundaries of their normal, i.e., minor, petty activities, which give no substantial relief to the workers, any attempt to meddle with capital, is invariably vetoed in the most emphatic manner by the central authorities of the bourgeois state.
And it is this fundamental mistake, this petty-bourgeois opportunism of the West-European Fabians, Possibilists, and Bernsteinians that is taken over by our advocates of municipalisation. (Power—Robert Greene)

  1. bourgeois intelligentsia

  2. a special trend

  3. the English Fabians

  4. class conciliation

  5. class antagonism


Correct Option: B
Explanation:

The pronoun ‘it’ is used for the noun phrase ‘a special trend’. A pronoun comes in place of a noun. So, this is the correct answer.

What is the most striking message one gets after reading this passage?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

Although it is generally best not to mix work with friendship, there are times when a friend can be used to greater effect than an enemy. A man of power, for example, often has dirty work that has to be done, but for the sake of appearances it is generally preferable to have other people do it for him; friends often do this the best, since their affection for him makes them willing to take chances. Also, if plans go awry for some reason, the friend can be used as a convenient scapegoat. This ‘fall of the favourite’ was a trick often used by kings and sovereigns. They would let their closest friend at court take the fall for a mistake, since the public would not believe that they would deliberately sacrifice a friend for such purpose. Of course, once the card is played out, the friend is lost forever. It is best, then, to reserve the scapegoat role for someone who is close but not too close.
Finally, the problem about working with friends is that it confuses the boundaries and distances that working requires. But if both partners in the arrangement understand the dangers involved, a friend often can be employed to great effect. One must never let one’s guard down in such a venture, however; always be on the lookout for any signs of emotional disturbance such as envy and ingratitude. Nothing is stable in the realm of power, and even the closest of friends can be transformed into the worst of enemies.
When a friend is hired, his qualities kept hidden for long and let it come to fore by and by. Strangely enough, it is the act of kindness that unbalances everything. People want to feel they deserve their good fortune. The receipt of a favour can become oppressive. He may get a feeling that he has been chosen because he is a friend and not because he merited it. There is almost a touch of condescension in the act of hiring friends that secretly afflicts them. The injury will come out slowly. A little more honesty, flashes of resent and envy here and there, and before it is realized the friendship has faded away. The more favours and gifts one bestows to revive friendship, the less gratitude is received.
Ingratitude has a long and deep history. It has demonstrated its powers for so many centuries, that it is truly amazing that people continue to underestimate them. Better to be wary. One should never expect gratitude from a friend. It will be a pleasant surprise to find that they are actually grateful. The problem with using or hiring friends is that it will inevitably limit the power one intended to have. The friend is rarely the one who is most able to help; and in the end, skill and competence are far more important than friendly feelings.
All working situations require a kind of distance between people. People try to work, not to make friends; friendliness (real or false) only obscures that fact. The key to power is the ability to judge who is best suited to further the interests of an organization in all situations. Keep friends for friendship, but work with the skilled and competent. (Robert Greene in Power)

  1. Friendship has no meaning in this world of business and intrigue.

  2. Friends play important role for those in pursuit of power.

  3. Friends are often used to do the dirty work for others in power.

  4. Those seeking power will not hesitate to use friends and then discard them.

  5. In a world of work and business, gratitude and loyalty do not count for much.


Correct Option: D
Explanation:

This is the most striking message one would get on reading the passage as it is about those who seek power and they would go to any extent to have that power and will use their friends as scapegoats and tools; use them and discard them once used.

What, according to the author, should one be wary of?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

Although it is generally best not to mix work with friendship, there are times when a friend can be used to greater effect than an enemy. A man of power, for example, often has dirty work that has to be done, but for the sake of appearances it is generally preferable to have other people do it for him; friends often do this the best, since their affection for him makes them willing to take chances. Also, if plans go awry for some reason, the friend can be used as a convenient scapegoat. This ‘fall of the favourite’ was a trick often used by kings and sovereigns. They would let their closest friend at court take the fall for a mistake, since the public would not believe that they would deliberately sacrifice a friend for such purpose. Of course, once the card is played out, the friend is lost forever. It is best, then, to reserve the scapegoat role for someone who is close but not too close.
Finally, the problem about working with friends is that it confuses the boundaries and distances that working requires. But if both partners in the arrangement understand the dangers involved, a friend often can be employed to great effect. One must never let one’s guard down in such a venture, however; always be on the lookout for any signs of emotional disturbance such as envy and ingratitude. Nothing is stable in the realm of power, and even the closest of friends can be transformed into the worst of enemies.
When a friend is hired, his qualities kept hidden for long and let it come to fore by and by. Strangely enough, it is the act of kindness that unbalances everything. People want to feel they deserve their good fortune. The receipt of a favour can become oppressive. He may get a feeling that he has been chosen because he is a friend and not because he merited it. There is almost a touch of condescension in the act of hiring friends that secretly afflicts them. The injury will come out slowly. A little more honesty, flashes of resent and envy here and there, and before it is realized the friendship has faded away. The more favours and gifts one bestows to revive friendship, the less gratitude is received.
Ingratitude has a long and deep history. It has demonstrated its powers for so many centuries, that it is truly amazing that people continue to underestimate them. Better to be wary. One should never expect gratitude from a friend. It will be a pleasant surprise to find that they are actually grateful. The problem with using or hiring friends is that it will inevitably limit the power one intended to have. The friend is rarely the one who is most able to help; and in the end, skill and competence are far more important than friendly feelings.
All working situations require a kind of distance between people. People try to work, not to make friends; friendliness (real or false) only obscures that fact. The key to power is the ability to judge who is best suited to further the interests of an organization in all situations. Keep friends for friendship, but work with the skilled and competent. (Robert Greene in Power)

  1. Dependence on friends for dirty works

  2. Tactful employment of friends

  3. Impact of ingratitude

  4. Mixing of work with friendship

  5. Expertise of friends


Correct Option: C
Explanation:

It is the ingratitude that the author asks one to be wary of, for when the matter comes to a crunch, it is ingratitude that comes into force. This is the answer.

According to the passage, is the ‘needs of the population’ avowed principle of the bourgeois that the author refers to?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows:

The bourgeois intelligentsia of the West, like the English Fabians, elevates municipal socialism to a special ‘trend’ precisely because it dreams of social peace, of class conciliation, and seeks to divert public attention away from the fundamental questions of the economic system as a whole, and of the state structure as a whole, to minor questions of local self-government. In the sphere of questions in the first category, the class antagonisms stand out most sharply; that is the sphere which affects the very foundations of the class rule of the bourgeoisie. Hence it is in that sphere that the philistine, reactionary utopia of bringing about socialism piecemeal is particularly hopeless. Attention is diverted to the sphere of minor local questions, being directed not to the question of the class rule of the bourgeoisie, nor to the question of the chief instruments of that rule, but to the question of distributing the crumbs thrown by the rich bourgeoisie for the ‘needs of the population.’ Naturally, since attention is focussed on such questions as the spending of paltry sums (in comparison with the total surplus value and total state expenditure of the bourgeoisie), which the bourgeoisie itself is willing to set aside for public health, or for education (the bourgeoisie must have trained workers able to adapt themselves to a high technical level!), and so on, it is possible, in the sphere of such minor questions, to hold forth about ‘social peace’, about the harmfulness of the class struggle, and so on. What class struggle can there be if the bourgeoisie itself is spending money on the ‘needs of the population’, on public health, on education? What needs is there for a social if it is possible through the local self-governing bodies, gradually, step by step, to extend ‘collective ownership’, and ‘socialistic’ production: the horse tramways, the slaughter-houses etc?
The philistine opportunism of that ‘trend’ lies in the fact that people forget the narrow limits of the so-called ‘municipal socialism’ (in reality, municipal capitalism, as the English Social-Democrats properly point out in their controversies with the Fabians). They forget that so long as the bourgeoisie rules as a class it cannot allow any encroachment, even from the ‘municipal’ point of view, upon the real foundations of its rule; that if the bourgeoisie allows, tolerates, ‘municipal socialism’, it is because the latter does not touch the foundations of its rule, does not interfere with the important sources of its wealth, but extends only to the narrow sphere of local expenditure, which the bourgeoisie itself allows the ‘population’ to manage. It does not need more than a slight acquaintance with ‘municipal socialism’ in the West to know that any attempt on the part of socialist municipalities to go a little beyond the boundaries of their normal, i.e., minor, petty activities, which give no substantial relief to the workers, any attempt to meddle with capital, is invariably vetoed in the most emphatic manner by the central authorities of the bourgeois state.
And it is this fundamental mistake, this petty-bourgeois opportunism of the West-European Fabians, Possibilists, and Bernsteinians that is taken over by our advocates of municipalisation. (Power—Robert Greene)

  1. It is a pejoratively stated position of the rich bourgeois.

  2. It is an honest declaration of intent by the bourgeois.

  3. It is elevation of municipal socialism to a special trend.

  4. It is a reference to reactionary utopia of piecemeal socialism.

  5. It is a reference to the kind of socialism ushered in by the bourgeois.


Correct Option: A
Explanation:

It is a pejoratively stated position of the rich bourgeois. The use of the word ‘crumb’ makes it abundantly clear and it adequately answers the question.

Which of the following is the chief reason for the bourgeois intelligentsia to seek to elevate municipal socialism to a special ‘trend’?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows:

The bourgeois intelligentsia of the West, like the English Fabians, elevates municipal socialism to a special ‘trend’ precisely because it dreams of social peace, of class conciliation, and seeks to divert public attention away from the fundamental questions of the economic system as a whole, and of the state structure as a whole, to minor questions of local self-government. In the sphere of questions in the first category, the class antagonisms stand out most sharply; that is the sphere which affects the very foundations of the class rule of the bourgeoisie. Hence it is in that sphere that the philistine, reactionary utopia of bringing about socialism piecemeal is particularly hopeless. Attention is diverted to the sphere of minor local questions, being directed not to the question of the class rule of the bourgeoisie, nor to the question of the chief instruments of that rule, but to the question of distributing the crumbs thrown by the rich bourgeoisie for the ‘needs of the population.’ Naturally, since attention is focussed on such questions as the spending of paltry sums (in comparison with the total surplus value and total state expenditure of the bourgeoisie), which the bourgeoisie itself is willing to set aside for public health, or for education (the bourgeoisie must have trained workers able to adapt themselves to a high technical level!), and so on, it is possible, in the sphere of such minor questions, to hold forth about ‘social peace’, about the harmfulness of the class struggle, and so on. What class struggle can there be if the bourgeoisie itself is spending money on the ‘needs of the population’, on public health, on education? What needs is there for a social if it is possible through the local self-governing bodies, gradually, step by step, to extend ‘collective ownership’, and ‘socialistic’ production: the horse tramways, the slaughter-houses etc?
The philistine opportunism of that ‘trend’ lies in the fact that people forget the narrow limits of the so-called ‘municipal socialism’ (in reality, municipal capitalism, as the English Social-Democrats properly point out in their controversies with the Fabians). They forget that so long as the bourgeoisie rules as a class it cannot allow any encroachment, even from the ‘municipal’ point of view, upon the real foundations of its rule; that if the bourgeoisie allows, tolerates, ‘municipal socialism’, it is because the latter does not touch the foundations of its rule, does not interfere with the important sources of its wealth, but extends only to the narrow sphere of local expenditure, which the bourgeoisie itself allows the ‘population’ to manage. It does not need more than a slight acquaintance with ‘municipal socialism’ in the West to know that any attempt on the part of socialist municipalities to go a little beyond the boundaries of their normal, i.e., minor, petty activities, which give no substantial relief to the workers, any attempt to meddle with capital, is invariably vetoed in the most emphatic manner by the central authorities of the bourgeois state.
And it is this fundamental mistake, this petty-bourgeois opportunism of the West-European Fabians, Possibilists, and Bernsteinians that is taken over by our advocates of municipalisation. (Power—Robert Greene)

  1. Desire to provide for public health and education

  2. Traversing through the narrow limits of municipal socialism

  3. Sidestepping the fundamental questions of the economic system

  4. Holding forth to social peace by highlighting the harmfulness of class struggle

  5. Promise of collective ownership and socialistic production through the local self-governing bodies


Correct Option: D
Explanation:

This is the chief reason because they want social peace at any cost and therefore, they must educate on the harmful effects of any class struggle. This is a façade they wish to erect to obfuscate the real issues. Not the correct answer.

What is the underlying idea of the passage?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows:

The bourgeois intelligentsia of the West, like the English Fabians, elevates municipal socialism to a special ‘trend’ precisely because it dreams of social peace, of class conciliation, and seeks to divert public attention away from the fundamental questions of the economic system as a whole, and of the state structure as a whole, to minor questions of local self-government. In the sphere of questions in the first category, the class antagonisms stand out most sharply; that is the sphere which affects the very foundations of the class rule of the bourgeoisie. Hence it is in that sphere that the philistine, reactionary utopia of bringing about socialism piecemeal is particularly hopeless. Attention is diverted to the sphere of minor local questions, being directed not to the question of the class rule of the bourgeoisie, nor to the question of the chief instruments of that rule, but to the question of distributing the crumbs thrown by the rich bourgeoisie for the ‘needs of the population.’ Naturally, since attention is focussed on such questions as the spending of paltry sums (in comparison with the total surplus value and total state expenditure of the bourgeoisie), which the bourgeoisie itself is willing to set aside for public health, or for education (the bourgeoisie must have trained workers able to adapt themselves to a high technical level!), and so on, it is possible, in the sphere of such minor questions, to hold forth about ‘social peace’, about the harmfulness of the class struggle, and so on. What class struggle can there be if the bourgeoisie itself is spending money on the ‘needs of the population’, on public health, on education? What needs is there for a social if it is possible through the local self-governing bodies, gradually, step by step, to extend ‘collective ownership’, and ‘socialistic’ production: the horse tramways, the slaughter-houses etc?
The philistine opportunism of that ‘trend’ lies in the fact that people forget the narrow limits of the so-called ‘municipal socialism’ (in reality, municipal capitalism, as the English Social-Democrats properly point out in their controversies with the Fabians). They forget that so long as the bourgeoisie rules as a class it cannot allow any encroachment, even from the ‘municipal’ point of view, upon the real foundations of its rule; that if the bourgeoisie allows, tolerates, ‘municipal socialism’, it is because the latter does not touch the foundations of its rule, does not interfere with the important sources of its wealth, but extends only to the narrow sphere of local expenditure, which the bourgeoisie itself allows the ‘population’ to manage. It does not need more than a slight acquaintance with ‘municipal socialism’ in the West to know that any attempt on the part of socialist municipalities to go a little beyond the boundaries of their normal, i.e., minor, petty activities, which give no substantial relief to the workers, any attempt to meddle with capital, is invariably vetoed in the most emphatic manner by the central authorities of the bourgeois state.
And it is this fundamental mistake, this petty-bourgeois opportunism of the West-European Fabians, Possibilists, and Bernsteinians that is taken over by our advocates of municipalisation. (Power—Robert Greene)

  1. To demonstrate that the rich bourgeois wanted to create an egalitarian society

  2. To highlight the harmful effects of class struggle on the economic health of a nation

  3. To show that the concerns of the bourgeois was just a ploy to buy social peace

  4. To suggest that there were no issues between the bourgeois and the votaries of municipal socialists

  5. To draw attention to the schism that prevailed between the ruling bourgeois and others


Correct Option: C
Explanation:

The concerns shown by the bourgeois were not genuine and that they were aimed at buying social peace. This is the central idea of the passage.

What is the central theme of the passage?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

It is no antiquarian pedantry that traces the origin of parliament back to Saxon times. For the tradition that the king must govern with the advice of his great men was already well established when the Conqueror arrived, and his Great Council not only included men who had been of the Council of Edward the Confessor, but was rightly regarded by Englishmen as the constitutional equivalent of  the witena gemot.
Feudalism was basically a system of land tenure by which the freeman held land from his lord in return for certain services – military and other – and the lord in his turn owed service to the king as overlord. But it was much more than a system of land tenure. Feudalism was a whole way of life – a social system in which lord and vassal were bound together by the closest possible ties. In the oath of homage the vassal swore ‘to become your man for the tenement I hold of you and to bear faith to you of life and members and earthly honours against all other men. The effect of this relationship was to bring into being a community of tenants with the lord at its centre. This community found its concrete expression in the honorial court, to which the tenants were bound to come and wherein the lord was entitled to their advice. When, therefore, we are told, the Conqueror asserted his lordship over every acre of the land, he thereby brought into being a single feudal community, the honour of England, His vassals, alias tenants-in-chief, alias barons, as members of this feudal community, owed duty of attendance and advice in the royal court.
Royal courts were held thrice a year on the solemn occasions at Christmas, Easter and Whitsun when the Normal kings wore their crowns. The chronicler tells us that there were present ‘all great men of England, archbishops, bishops, earls, thegns and knights.’ It is well known that from the earliest times a special notification of summons was sent to each tenant-in-chief and there were penalties for non-attendance. At these courts pleas were judged and decisions taken on matters of state. The tradition of these great courts at the crown-wearings was never quite lost. A hundred years later, in 1176, Henry II held his Christmas court at Nottingham and immediately afterwards held a great council with bishops, earls and barons of the kingdom, at which various great business was done; and when, in the middle of the next century (in 1258), the barons at Oxford demanded three parliaments a year they were harking back to the old thrice-yearly crown-wearing courts.
In the intervals between these great national assemblies, and for the ordinary business of government, the king relied upon a small number of personal advisers. These advisers were the members of the royal household and essentially, therefore, royal servants. In the Norman and Angevin periods, these household officers were normally drawn from the ranks of the baronage, but with the growing complexity of administration, several of the most important offices, notably those of the chancellor, the treasurer and the justices, came to be held by officials – men of non-baronial rank with professional qualifications. At the same time, this little group of personal advisers began to acquire an organisation of its own and we can speak of a ‘council’ rather than of ‘counsellors’. (British Parliament)

  1. This is a looking back into the pages of history to understand the system of feudalism in England.

  2. The passage is an attempt to trace the historical events leading to the evolution of the British Parliament.

  3. The theme of the passage revolves around the idea of council and counsellors.

  4. Contributions of Norman and Angevin periods in the creation of the British Parliament.

  5. The British parliament had not evolved in a day.


Correct Option: B
Explanation:

In essence, the passage traces the origin of the British Parliament. This is the correct answer.

The author says that tracing back the origin of parliament to Saxon times would not be an antiquarian pedantry. Does he, according to the passage, encourage or discourage this exercise of tracing back the origin?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

It is no antiquarian pedantry that traces the origin of parliament back to Saxon times. For the tradition that the king must govern with the advice of his great men was already well established when the Conqueror arrived, and his Great Council not only included men who had been of the Council of Edward the Confessor, but was rightly regarded by Englishmen as the constitutional equivalent of  the witena gemot.
Feudalism was basically a system of land tenure by which the freeman held land from his lord in return for certain services – military and other – and the lord in his turn owed service to the king as overlord. But it was much more than a system of land tenure. Feudalism was a whole way of life – a social system in which lord and vassal were bound together by the closest possible ties. In the oath of homage the vassal swore ‘to become your man for the tenement I hold of you and to bear faith to you of life and members and earthly honours against all other men. The effect of this relationship was to bring into being a community of tenants with the lord at its centre. This community found its concrete expression in the honorial court, to which the tenants were bound to come and wherein the lord was entitled to their advice. When, therefore, we are told, the Conqueror asserted his lordship over every acre of the land, he thereby brought into being a single feudal community, the honour of England, His vassals, alias tenants-in-chief, alias barons, as members of this feudal community, owed duty of attendance and advice in the royal court.
Royal courts were held thrice a year on the solemn occasions at Christmas, Easter and Whitsun when the Normal kings wore their crowns. The chronicler tells us that there were present ‘all great men of England, archbishops, bishops, earls, thegns and knights.’ It is well known that from the earliest times a special notification of summons was sent to each tenant-in-chief and there were penalties for non-attendance. At these courts pleas were judged and decisions taken on matters of state. The tradition of these great courts at the crown-wearings was never quite lost. A hundred years later, in 1176, Henry II held his Christmas court at Nottingham and immediately afterwards held a great council with bishops, earls and barons of the kingdom, at which various great business was done; and when, in the middle of the next century (in 1258), the barons at Oxford demanded three parliaments a year they were harking back to the old thrice-yearly crown-wearing courts.
In the intervals between these great national assemblies, and for the ordinary business of government, the king relied upon a small number of personal advisers. These advisers were the members of the royal household and essentially, therefore, royal servants. In the Norman and Angevin periods, these household officers were normally drawn from the ranks of the baronage, but with the growing complexity of administration, several of the most important offices, notably those of the chancellor, the treasurer and the justices, came to be held by officials – men of non-baronial rank with professional qualifications. At the same time, this little group of personal advisers began to acquire an organisation of its own and we can speak of a ‘council’ rather than of ‘counsellors’. (British Parliament)

  1. There is no clear indication as to what exactly the writer suggests. The question is irrelevant.

  2. The writer apparently discourages any attempt to trace back the origin of parliament to Saxon times as facts are far too apparent.

  3. The writer clearly indicates that it would not be an exercise in futility to trace back the origin of parliament by way of a research work.

  4. The question of encouraging or discouraging did not arise as the author has made an objective analysis of certain historical facts.

  5. The matter of research is not a matter of encouragement or discouragement as this is a matter of academic interest.


Correct Option: C
Explanation:

When the writer says it would not be an antiquarian pedantry to trace back the origin, he indirectly suggests that such an exercise can be undertaken. It may, therefore be said that, he encourages such an exercise. This fits the bill.

According to the passage, the writer alludes to a tradition that he so approvingly speaks of. It is

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

It is no antiquarian pedantry that traces the origin of parliament back to Saxon times. For the tradition that the king must govern with the advice of his great men was already well established when the Conqueror arrived, and his Great Council not only included men who had been of the Council of Edward the Confessor, but was rightly regarded by Englishmen as the constitutional equivalent of  the witena gemot.
Feudalism was basically a system of land tenure by which the freeman held land from his lord in return for certain services – military and other – and the lord in his turn owed service to the king as overlord. But it was much more than a system of land tenure. Feudalism was a whole way of life – a social system in which lord and vassal were bound together by the closest possible ties. In the oath of homage the vassal swore ‘to become your man for the tenement I hold of you and to bear faith to you of life and members and earthly honours against all other men. The effect of this relationship was to bring into being a community of tenants with the lord at its centre. This community found its concrete expression in the honorial court, to which the tenants were bound to come and wherein the lord was entitled to their advice. When, therefore, we are told, the Conqueror asserted his lordship over every acre of the land, he thereby brought into being a single feudal community, the honour of England, His vassals, alias tenants-in-chief, alias barons, as members of this feudal community, owed duty of attendance and advice in the royal court.
Royal courts were held thrice a year on the solemn occasions at Christmas, Easter and Whitsun when the Normal kings wore their crowns. The chronicler tells us that there were present ‘all great men of England, archbishops, bishops, earls, thegns and knights.’ It is well known that from the earliest times a special notification of summons was sent to each tenant-in-chief and there were penalties for non-attendance. At these courts pleas were judged and decisions taken on matters of state. The tradition of these great courts at the crown-wearings was never quite lost. A hundred years later, in 1176, Henry II held his Christmas court at Nottingham and immediately afterwards held a great council with bishops, earls and barons of the kingdom, at which various great business was done; and when, in the middle of the next century (in 1258), the barons at Oxford demanded three parliaments a year they were harking back to the old thrice-yearly crown-wearing courts.
In the intervals between these great national assemblies, and for the ordinary business of government, the king relied upon a small number of personal advisers. These advisers were the members of the royal household and essentially, therefore, royal servants. In the Norman and Angevin periods, these household officers were normally drawn from the ranks of the baronage, but with the growing complexity of administration, several of the most important offices, notably those of the chancellor, the treasurer and the justices, came to be held by officials – men of non-baronial rank with professional qualifications. At the same time, this little group of personal advisers began to acquire an organisation of its own and we can speak of a ‘council’ rather than of ‘counsellors’. (British Parliament)

  1. respect shown as a matter of course to the rulers on the matters of divinity

  2. practice of making kings cling to the matters of traditions long established

  3. the parliamentary practices of advising kings on the matters of governance

  4. recognition of Great Council as constitutional equivalent of witena gemot

  5. importance of feudalism in the matters of day-to-day functioning of the government


Correct Option: D
Explanation:

It is this Great Council that the writer is so approvingly speaking of. To quote the writer, he says ‘rightly regarded by Englishmen as the constitutional equivalent of the 'witena gemot’. The use of the word ‘rightly’ by the writer shows his approval. This is the correct answer.

As per the passage, the Norman and Angevin periods are notable for

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

It is no antiquarian pedantry that traces the origin of parliament back to Saxon times. For the tradition that the king must govern with the advice of his great men was already well established when the Conqueror arrived, and his Great Council not only included men who had been of the Council of Edward the Confessor, but was rightly regarded by Englishmen as the constitutional equivalent of  the witena gemot.
Feudalism was basically a system of land tenure by which the freeman held land from his lord in return for certain services – military and other – and the lord in his turn owed service to the king as overlord. But it was much more than a system of land tenure. Feudalism was a whole way of life – a social system in which lord and vassal were bound together by the closest possible ties. In the oath of homage the vassal swore ‘to become your man for the tenement I hold of you and to bear faith to you of life and members and earthly honours against all other men. The effect of this relationship was to bring into being a community of tenants with the lord at its centre. This community found its concrete expression in the honorial court, to which the tenants were bound to come and wherein the lord was entitled to their advice. When, therefore, we are told, the Conqueror asserted his lordship over every acre of the land, he thereby brought into being a single feudal community, the honour of England, His vassals, alias tenants-in-chief, alias barons, as members of this feudal community, owed duty of attendance and advice in the royal court.
Royal courts were held thrice a year on the solemn occasions at Christmas, Easter and Whitsun when the Normal kings wore their crowns. The chronicler tells us that there were present ‘all great men of England, archbishops, bishops, earls, thegns and knights.’ It is well known that from the earliest times a special notification of summons was sent to each tenant-in-chief and there were penalties for non-attendance. At these courts pleas were judged and decisions taken on matters of state. The tradition of these great courts at the crown-wearings was never quite lost. A hundred years later, in 1176, Henry II held his Christmas court at Nottingham and immediately afterwards held a great council with bishops, earls and barons of the kingdom, at which various great business was done; and when, in the middle of the next century (in 1258), the barons at Oxford demanded three parliaments a year they were harking back to the old thrice-yearly crown-wearing courts.
In the intervals between these great national assemblies, and for the ordinary business of government, the king relied upon a small number of personal advisers. These advisers were the members of the royal household and essentially, therefore, royal servants. In the Norman and Angevin periods, these household officers were normally drawn from the ranks of the baronage, but with the growing complexity of administration, several of the most important offices, notably those of the chancellor, the treasurer and the justices, came to be held by officials – men of non-baronial rank with professional qualifications. At the same time, this little group of personal advisers began to acquire an organisation of its own and we can speak of a ‘council’ rather than of ‘counsellors’. (British Parliament)

  1. clinging on to the practices of drawing advisers from the royal household

  2. switching over to the concept of council from the idea of counsellors

  3. doggedly holding on to the principle of baronial rank officials

  4. reliance on men of non-baronial rank with professional qualifications

  5. ignoring the importance of growing complexity of administration


Correct Option: D
Explanation:

The period is notable for this important shift whereby it chose to rely more on professional qualifications than on royal household. This is the correct answer.

Why did the author term the demand of Christopher Columbus of being called “Grand Admiral of the Ocean” as insanely bold?

Directions: Answer the given question based on the following passage:

Most of us are timid. We want to avoid tension and conflict and we want to be liked by all. We may contemplate a bold action but we rarely bring it to life. We are terrified of the consequences, of what others might think of us, of the hostility we will stir up if we dare to go beyond our usual place.
Although we may disguise our timidity as a concern for others, a desire not to hurt or offend them, in fact it is the opposite—we are really self-absorbed, worried about ourselves and how others perceive us. Boldness, on the other hand, is outer-directed, and often makes people feel more at ease, since it is less self-conscious and less repressed.
Few are born bold. Even Napoleon had to cultivate the habit on the battlefield, where he knew it was a matter of life and death. In social setting he was awkward and timid, but he overcame this and practised boldness in every part of his life because he saw its tremendous power, how it could literally enlarge a man (even one who, like Napoleon, was in fact conspicuously small).
We must practise and develop boldness. There are immense uses for it. The best place to begin is often the delicate world of negotiation, particularly those discussions in which we are asked to set our price. How often we put ourselves down by asking for too little. When Christopher Columbus proposed that the Spanish court finance his voyage to the Americans, he also made the insanely bold demand that he be called ‘Grand Admiral of the Ocean.’ The court agreed. The price he set was the price he received—he demanded to be treated with respect, and so he was. Henry Kissinger too knew that in negotiation, bold demands work better than starting off with piecemeal concessions and trying to meet the other person halfway. We must set our value high, and then, as Count Lusting did, set it higher.
If boldness is not natural, neither is timidity. It is an acquired habit, picked up out of a desire to avoid conflict. If timidity has taken hold, then, it must be rooted out. Fears of consequences of a bold action are way out of proportion to reality, and in fact the consequences of timidity are worse. When value is lowered, we create a self-fulfilling cycle of doubt and disaster. The problems created by an audacious move can be disguised, even remedied, with more and greater audacity. (Modified and extracted from Power—Robert Greene)

  1. Sane people never make such insane demands.

  2. Columbus was suffering from an unsound mind.

  3. It was a kind of impossible demand to make but Columbus had the temerity to make it.

  4. Columbus ran the risk of being declared an offender by the Spanish court.

  5. The kind of boldness Columbus showed was nothing but insanity.


Correct Option: C
Explanation:

It was the kind of boldness shown by Columbus that made the author use this phrase to describe his demand. It would seem almost impossible to meet and yet Columbus was bold enough to make it.

According to the author, which of the following is true in context of the passage?

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows:

The bourgeois intelligentsia of the West, like the English Fabians, elevates municipal socialism to a special ‘trend’ precisely because it dreams of social peace, of class conciliation, and seeks to divert public attention away from the fundamental questions of the economic system as a whole, and of the state structure as a whole, to minor questions of local self-government. In the sphere of questions in the first category, the class antagonisms stand out most sharply; that is the sphere which affects the very foundations of the class rule of the bourgeoisie. Hence it is in that sphere that the philistine, reactionary utopia of bringing about socialism piecemeal is particularly hopeless. Attention is diverted to the sphere of minor local questions, being directed not to the question of the class rule of the bourgeoisie, nor to the question of the chief instruments of that rule, but to the question of distributing the crumbs thrown by the rich bourgeoisie for the ‘needs of the population.’ Naturally, since attention is focussed on such questions as the spending of paltry sums (in comparison with the total surplus value and total state expenditure of the bourgeoisie), which the bourgeoisie itself is willing to set aside for public health, or for education (the bourgeoisie must have trained workers able to adapt themselves to a high technical level!), and so on, it is possible, in the sphere of such minor questions, to hold forth about ‘social peace’, about the harmfulness of the class struggle, and so on. What class struggle can there be if the bourgeoisie itself is spending money on the ‘needs of the population’, on public health, on education? What needs is there for a social if it is possible through the local self-governing bodies, gradually, step by step, to extend ‘collective ownership’, and ‘socialistic’ production: the horse tramways, the slaughter-houses etc?
The philistine opportunism of that ‘trend’ lies in the fact that people forget the narrow limits of the so-called ‘municipal socialism’ (in reality, municipal capitalism, as the English Social-Democrats properly point out in their controversies with the Fabians). They forget that so long as the bourgeoisie rules as a class it cannot allow any encroachment, even from the ‘municipal’ point of view, upon the real foundations of its rule; that if the bourgeoisie allows, tolerates, ‘municipal socialism’, it is because the latter does not touch the foundations of its rule, does not interfere with the important sources of its wealth, but extends only to the narrow sphere of local expenditure, which the bourgeoisie itself allows the ‘population’ to manage. It does not need more than a slight acquaintance with ‘municipal socialism’ in the West to know that any attempt on the part of socialist municipalities to go a little beyond the boundaries of their normal, i.e., minor, petty activities, which give no substantial relief to the workers, any attempt to meddle with capital, is invariably vetoed in the most emphatic manner by the central authorities of the bourgeois state.
And it is this fundamental mistake, this petty-bourgeois opportunism of the West-European Fabians, Possibilists, and Bernsteinians that is taken over by our advocates of municipalisation. (Power—Robert Greene)

  1. The bourgeois intelligentsia was opposed to the idea of local self-government as it militated against their philosophy.

  2. The rich bourgeoisie went out of its way to address, without exception, the question of ‘the needs of the population’.

  3. The central authorities of the bourgeois state never missed an opportunity to meddle with the capital.

  4. It was the English Fabians who elevated municipal socialism to a high in order to float the concept of local self-government.

  5. It was a matter of general satisfaction for the people that the bourgeois took care of their basic human needs to offset any possible rancour.


Correct Option: D
Explanation:

Absolutely true as the bourgeois intelligentsia has merely followed what the English Fabians have long believed and practised. This is the correct answer.

Besides being a system of land tenure, feudalism, according to the passage, was a/an

Directions: Read the following passage and answer the question that follows.

It is no antiquarian pedantry that traces the origin of parliament back to Saxon times. For the tradition that the king must govern with the advice of his great men was already well established when the Conqueror arrived, and his Great Council not only included men who had been of the Council of Edward the Confessor, but was rightly regarded by Englishmen as the constitutional equivalent of  the witena gemot.
Feudalism was basically a system of land tenure by which the freeman held land from his lord in return for certain services – military and other – and the lord in his turn owed service to the king as overlord. But it was much more than a system of land tenure. Feudalism was a whole way of life – a social system in which lord and vassal were bound together by the closest possible ties. In the oath of homage the vassal swore ‘to become your man for the tenement I hold of you and to bear faith to you of life and members and earthly honours against all other men. The effect of this relationship was to bring into being a community of tenants with the lord at its centre. This community found its concrete expression in the honorial court, to which the tenants were bound to come and wherein the lord was entitled to their advice. When, therefore, we are told, the Conqueror asserted his lordship over every acre of the land, he thereby brought into being a single feudal community, the honour of England, His vassals, alias tenants-in-chief, alias barons, as members of this feudal community, owed duty of attendance and advice in the royal court.
Royal courts were held thrice a year on the solemn occasions at Christmas, Easter and Whitsun when the Normal kings wore their crowns. The chronicler tells us that there were present ‘all great men of England, archbishops, bishops, earls, thegns and knights.’ It is well known that from the earliest times a special notification of summons was sent to each tenant-in-chief and there were penalties for non-attendance. At these courts pleas were judged and decisions taken on matters of state. The tradition of these great courts at the crown-wearings was never quite lost. A hundred years later, in 1176, Henry II held his Christmas court at Nottingham and immediately afterwards held a great council with bishops, earls and barons of the kingdom, at which various great business was done; and when, in the middle of the next century (in 1258), the barons at Oxford demanded three parliaments a year they were harking back to the old thrice-yearly crown-wearing courts.
In the intervals between these great national assemblies, and for the ordinary business of government, the king relied upon a small number of personal advisers. These advisers were the members of the royal household and essentially, therefore, royal servants. In the Norman and Angevin periods, these household officers were normally drawn from the ranks of the baronage, but with the growing complexity of administration, several of the most important offices, notably those of the chancellor, the treasurer and the justices, came to be held by officials – men of non-baronial rank with professional qualifications. At the same time, this little group of personal advisers began to acquire an organisation of its own and we can speak of a ‘council’ rather than of ‘counsellors’. (British Parliament)

  1. social system binding lords and vassals

  2. way of life for both the ruled and the ruler

  3. commitment by vassals to do the bidding of lords

  4. undertaking by lords to safeguard interests of tenants

  5. relationship fostered to further one another’s interests


Correct Option: A
Explanation:

The author terms feudalism as a social system of binding lords and vassals in closest possible ties. This answers the question.

According to the passage, 'boldness' is

Directions: Answer the given question based on the following passage:

Most of us are timid. We want to avoid tension and conflict and we want to be liked by all. We may contemplate a bold action but we rarely bring it to life. We are terrified of the consequences, of what others might think of us, of the hostility we will stir up if we dare to go beyond our usual place.
Although we may disguise our timidity as a concern for others, a desire not to hurt or offend them, in fact it is the opposite—we are really self-absorbed, worried about ourselves and how others perceive us. Boldness, on the other hand, is outer-directed, and often makes people feel more at ease, since it is less self-conscious and less repressed.
Few are born bold. Even Napoleon had to cultivate the habit on the battlefield, where he knew it was a matter of life and death. In social setting he was awkward and timid, but he overcame this and practised boldness in every part of his life because he saw its tremendous power, how it could literally enlarge a man (even one who, like Napoleon, was in fact conspicuously small).
We must practise and develop boldness. There are immense uses for it. The best place to begin is often the delicate world of negotiation, particularly those discussions in which we are asked to set our price. How often we put ourselves down by asking for too little. When Christopher Columbus proposed that the Spanish court finance his voyage to the Americans, he also made the insanely bold demand that he be called ‘Grand Admiral of the Ocean.’ The court agreed. The price he set was the price he received—he demanded to be treated with respect, and so he was. Henry Kissinger too knew that in negotiation, bold demands work better than starting off with piecemeal concessions and trying to meet the other person halfway. We must set our value high, and then, as Count Lusting did, set it higher.
If boldness is not natural, neither is timidity. It is an acquired habit, picked up out of a desire to avoid conflict. If timidity has taken hold, then, it must be rooted out. Fears of consequences of a bold action are way out of proportion to reality, and in fact the consequences of timidity are worse. When value is lowered, we create a self-fulfilling cycle of doubt and disaster. The problems created by an audacious move can be disguised, even remedied, with more and greater audacity. (Modified and extracted from Power—Robert Greene)

  1. natural

  2. cultivated

  3. taught

  4. practised

  5. eulogised


Correct Option: B
Explanation:

It has to be cultivated or acquired in order to avoid conflict.

According to the author ‘most of us are timid’ because

Directions: Answer the given question based on the following passage:

Most of us are timid. We want to avoid tension and conflict and we want to be liked by all. We may contemplate a bold action but we rarely bring it to life. We are terrified of the consequences, of what others might think of us, of the hostility we will stir up if we dare to go beyond our usual place.
Although we may disguise our timidity as a concern for others, a desire not to hurt or offend them, in fact it is the opposite—we are really self-absorbed, worried about ourselves and how others perceive us. Boldness, on the other hand, is outer-directed, and often makes people feel more at ease, since it is less self-conscious and less repressed.
Few are born bold. Even Napoleon had to cultivate the habit on the battlefield, where he knew it was a matter of life and death. In social setting he was awkward and timid, but he overcame this and practised boldness in every part of his life because he saw its tremendous power, how it could literally enlarge a man (even one who, like Napoleon, was in fact conspicuously small).
We must practise and develop boldness. There are immense uses for it. The best place to begin is often the delicate world of negotiation, particularly those discussions in which we are asked to set our price. How often we put ourselves down by asking for too little. When Christopher Columbus proposed that the Spanish court finance his voyage to the Americans, he also made the insanely bold demand that he be called ‘Grand Admiral of the Ocean.’ The court agreed. The price he set was the price he received—he demanded to be treated with respect, and so he was. Henry Kissinger too knew that in negotiation, bold demands work better than starting off with piecemeal concessions and trying to meet the other person halfway. We must set our value high, and then, as Count Lusting did, set it higher.
If boldness is not natural, neither is timidity. It is an acquired habit, picked up out of a desire to avoid conflict. If timidity has taken hold, then, it must be rooted out. Fears of consequences of a bold action are way out of proportion to reality, and in fact the consequences of timidity are worse. When value is lowered, we create a self-fulfilling cycle of doubt and disaster. The problems created by an audacious move can be disguised, even remedied, with more and greater audacity. (Modified and extracted from Power—Robert Greene)

  1. timidity is a trait that comes at birth

  2. nature plants the germs of timidity

  3. fear of consequences makes us timid

  4. it does not always pay to be bold

  5. it works as an immediate safety device


Correct Option: C
Explanation:

Indeed, it is the fear of the consequences, what people would think of us makes us timid.

What is the central idea of the passage?

Directions: Answer the given question based on the following passage:

Most of us are timid. We want to avoid tension and conflict and we want to be liked by all. We may contemplate a bold action but we rarely bring it to life. We are terrified of the consequences, of what others might think of us, of the hostility we will stir up if we dare to go beyond our usual place.
Although we may disguise our timidity as a concern for others, a desire not to hurt or offend them, in fact it is the opposite—we are really self-absorbed, worried about ourselves and how others perceive us. Boldness, on the other hand, is outer-directed, and often makes people feel more at ease, since it is less self-conscious and less repressed.
Few are born bold. Even Napoleon had to cultivate the habit on the battlefield, where he knew it was a matter of life and death. In social setting he was awkward and timid, but he overcame this and practised boldness in every part of his life because he saw its tremendous power, how it could literally enlarge a man (even one who, like Napoleon, was in fact conspicuously small).
We must practise and develop boldness. There are immense uses for it. The best place to begin is often the delicate world of negotiation, particularly those discussions in which we are asked to set our price. How often we put ourselves down by asking for too little. When Christopher Columbus proposed that the Spanish court finance his voyage to the Americans, he also made the insanely bold demand that he be called ‘Grand Admiral of the Ocean.’ The court agreed. The price he set was the price he received—he demanded to be treated with respect, and so he was. Henry Kissinger too knew that in negotiation, bold demands work better than starting off with piecemeal concessions and trying to meet the other person halfway. We must set our value high, and then, as Count Lusting did, set it higher.
If boldness is not natural, neither is timidity. It is an acquired habit, picked up out of a desire to avoid conflict. If timidity has taken hold, then, it must be rooted out. Fears of consequences of a bold action are way out of proportion to reality, and in fact the consequences of timidity are worse. When value is lowered, we create a self-fulfilling cycle of doubt and disaster. The problems created by an audacious move can be disguised, even remedied, with more and greater audacity. (Modified and extracted from Power—Robert Greene)

  1. To demonstrate that ultimately it is boldness that prevails.

  2. To prove that being insanely bold is a good idea.

  3. To show that we all can be as successful as Casanova.

  4. To show that boldness is acquired and can be put to good use.

  5. To demonstrate that timidity and boldness are two sides of the same coin.


Correct Option: D
Explanation:

This is the central idea. Boldness is acquired and can be put to good use as Columbus did. This is the answer.

- Hide questions